Leibniz,
Gottfried Wilhelm
I INTRODUCTION
Leibniz, Gottfried
Wilhelm, also Leibnitz, Baron
Gottfried Wilhelm von (1646-1716), German philosopher, mathematician, and
statesman, regarded as one of the supreme intellects of the 17th century.
Leibniz was born in Leipzig. He was educated
at the universities of Leipzig, Jena, and Altdorf.
Beginning in 1666, the year in which he was awarded a doctorate in law, he
served Johann Philipp von Schönborn,
archbishop elector of Mainz, in a variety of legal, political, and diplomatic
capacities. In 1673, when the elector's reign ended, Leibniz went to Paris. He
remained there for three years and also visited Amsterdam and London, devoting
his time to the study of mathematics, science, and philosophy. In 1676 he was
appointed librarian and privy councillor at the court of Hannover.
For the 40 years until his death, he served Ernest Augustus, duke of Brunswick-Lüneburg, later elector of Hannover,
and George Louis, elector of Hannover, later George
I, king of Great Britain and Ireland.
Leibniz was considered a universal genius by his
contemporaries. His work encompasses not only mathematics and philosophy but
also theology, law, diplomacy, politics, history, philology, and physics.
II MATHEMATICS
Leibniz's contribution in mathematics was to discover, in
1675, the fundamental principles of infinitesimal calculus. This discovery was
arrived at independently of the discoveries of the English scientist Sir Isaac
Newton, whose system of calculus was invented in 1666. Leibniz's system was
published in 1684, Newton's in 1687, and the method of notation devised by
Leibniz was universally adopted (see Mathematical Symbols). In 1672 he
also invented a calculating machine capable of multiplying, dividing, and
extracting square roots, and he is considered a pioneer in the development of
mathematical logic.
III PHILOSOPHY
In the philosophy expounded by Leibniz, the universe
is composed of countless conscious centers of
spiritual force or energy, known as monads. Each monad represents an individual
microcosm, mirroring the universe in varying degrees of perfection and
developing independently of all other monads. The universe that these monads
constitute is the harmonious result of a divine plan. Humans, however, with
their limited vision, cannot accept such evils as disease and death as part of
a universal harmony. This Leibnizian universe, “the
best of all possible worlds,” is satirized as a utopia by the French author
Voltaire in his novel Candide (1759).
Important philosophical works by Leibniz include Essays in
Theodicy on the Goodness of God, the Liberty of Man, and the Origin of Evil
(2 volumes, 1710; translated in Philosophical Works,1890), Monadology (1714; published in Latin as Principia
Philosophiae,1721; translated 1890), and New Essays Concerning Human
Understanding (1703; published 1765; translated 1916). The latter two greatly
influenced German philosophers of the 18th century, including Christian von
Wolff and Immanuel Kant.
Microsoft ® Encarta ® Reference Library 2003.
© 1993-2002 Microsoft Corporation. All rights reserved.
Leibniz,
Gottfried Wilhelm
b. July 1 [June 21, old style], 1646, Leipzig
d. Nov. 14, 1716, Hannover,
Hanover
German philosopher, mathematician, and political adviser,
important both as a metaphysician and as a logician and distinguished also for
his independent invention of the differential and integral calculus.
Leibniz was born into a pious Lutheran family near the end of the
Thirty Years' War, which had laid Germany in ruins. As a child, he was educated
in the Nicolai School but was largely self-taught in
the library of his father, who had died in 1652. At Easter time in 1661, he
entered the University of Leipzig as a law student; there he came into contact
with the thought of men who had revolutionized science and philosophy--men such
as Galileo, Francis Bacon, Thomas Hobbes, and René Descartes. Leibniz
dreamed of reconciling--a verb that he did not hesitate to use time and again
throughout his career--these modern thinkers with the Aristotle of the
Scholastics. His baccalaureate thesis, De Principio
Individui ("On the Principle of the
Individual"), which appeared in May 1663, was inspired partly by Lutheran nominalism (the theory that universals have no reality
but are mere names) and emphasized the existential value of the individual,
who is not to be explained either by matter alone or by form alone but rather
by his whole being (entitate tota). This notion was the first germ of the future
"monad." In 1666 he wrote De
Arte Combinatoria ("On the Art of
Combination"), in which he formulated a model that is the theoretical
ancestor of some modern computers: all reasoning, all discovery, verbal or not,
is reducible to an ordered combination of elements, such as numbers, words,
sounds, or colours.
After completing
his legal studies in 1666, Leibniz applied for the degree of doctor of
law. He was refused because of his age and consequently left his native city
forever. At Altdorf--the university town of the free
city of Nürnberg--his dissertation De Casibus Perplexis ("On
Perplexing Cases") procured him the doctor's degree at once, as well as
the immediate offer of a professor's chair, which, however, he declined. During
his stay in Nürnberg, he met Johann Christian, Freiherr von Boyneburg, one of the most distinguished German statesmen
of the day. Boyneburg took him into his service and
introduced him to the court of the prince elector, the archbishop of Mainz,
Johann Philipp von Schönborn,
where he was concerned with questions of law and politics.
King Louis
XIV of France was a growing threat to the German Holy Roman Empire. To ward
off this danger and divert the King's interests elsewhere, the Archbishop hoped
to propose to Louis a project for an expedition into Egypt; because he was
using religion as a pretext, he expressed the hope that the project would
promote the reunion of the church. Leibniz, with a view toward this
reunion, worked on the Demonstrationes Catholicae. His research led him to situate the soul in
a point--this was new progress toward the monad--and to develop the principle
of sufficient reason (nothing occurs without a reason). His meditations on
the difficult theory of the point were related to problems encountered in
optics, space, and movement;
they were published in 1671 under the general title Hypothesis Physica Nova ("New Physical Hypothesis"). He
asserted that movement depends, as in the theory of the German astronomer
Johannes Kepler, on the action of a spirit (God).
In 1672 the
Elector sent the young jurist on a mission to Paris, where he arrived at the
end of March. In September, Leibniz met with Antoine
Arnauld, a Jansenist
theologian (Jansenism
was a nonorthodox Roman Catholic movement that
spawned a rigoristic form of morality) known for his
writings against the Jesuits. Leibniz sought Arnauld's
help for the reunion of the church. He was soon left without protectors by the
deaths of Freiherr von Boyneburg
in December 1672 and of the Elector of Mainz in February 1673; he was now,
however, free to pursue his scientific studies. In search of financial support,
he constructed a calculating machine and presented it to the Royal Society
during his first journey to London, in 1673.
Late in 1675 Leibniz
laid the foundations of both integral and differential calculus.
With this discovery, he ceased to consider time and space as
substances--another step closer to monadology. He
began to develop the notion that the concepts of extension
and motion contained an element of the imaginary, so that the basic laws of
motion could not be discovered merely from a study of their nature.
Nevertheless, he continued to hold that extension and motion could provide a
means for explaining and predicting the course of phenomena. Thus, contrary to Descartes,
Leibniz held that it would not be contradictory to posit that this world
is a well-related dream. If visible movement depends on the imaginary element
found in the concept of extension, it can no longer be defined by simple local
movement; it must be the result of a force. In criticizing the Cartesian formulation
of the laws of motion, known as mechanics, Leibniz became, in 1676, the
founder of a new formulation, known as dynamics,
which substituted kinetic energy for the conservation of movement. At the same
time, beginning with the principle that light follows the path of least
resistance, he believed that he could demonstrate the ordering of nature toward
a final goal or cause.
Leibniz continued
his work but was still without an income-producing position. By October 1676,
however, he had accepted a position in the employment of John Frederick, the
duke of Braunschweig-Lüneburg. John Frederick, a convert
to Catholicism from Lutheranism in 1651, had become duke of Hanover in 1665. He
appointed Leibniz librarian, but, beginning in February 1677, Leibniz solicited
the post of councillor, which he was finally granted in 1678. It should be
noted that, among the great philosophers of his time, he was the only one who
had to earn a living. As a result, he was always a jack-of-all-trades to
royalty.
Trying to make himself useful in all ways, Leibniz proposed that education
be made more practical, that academies be founded; he worked on hydraulic
presses, windmills, lamps, submarines, clocks, and a wide variety of mechanical
devices; he devised a means of perfecting carriages and experimented with
phosphorus. He also developed a water pump run by windmills, which ameliorated
the exploitation of the mines of the Harz Mountains,
and he worked in these mines as an engineer frequently from 1680 to 1685.
Leibniz is considered to be among the creators of geology because of the
observations he compiled there, including the hypothesis that the Earth was at
first molten. These many occupations did not stop his work in mathematics: In
March 1679 he perfected the binary system of numeration (i.e., using two
as a base), and at the end of the same year he proposed the basis for analysis situs, now known as general
topology, a branch of mathematics that deals with selected properties of
collections of related physical or abstract elements. He was also working on
his dynamics and his philosophy, which was becoming increasingly
anti-Cartesian. At this point, Duke John Frederick died on Jan. 7, 1680, and
his brother, Ernest
Augustus I, succeeded him.
France was
growing more intolerant at home--from 1680 to 1682 there were harsh
persecutions of the Protestants that paved the way for the revocation of the
Edict of Nantes on Oct. 18, 1685--and increasingly menacing on its frontiers,
for as early as 1681, despite the reigning peace, Louis XIV took Strasbourg and
laid claim to 10 cities in Alsace. France was thus becoming a real danger to
the empire, which had already been shaken on the east by a Hungarian revolt and
by the advance of the Turks, who had been stopped only by the victory of John
III Sobieski, king of Poland, at the siege of Vienna
in 1683. Leibniz served both his prince and the empire as a patriot. He
suggested to his prince a means of increasing the production of linen and
proposed a process for the desalinization of water; he recommended classifying
the archives and wrote, in both French and Latin, a violent pamphlet against
Louis XIV.
During this same
period Leibniz continued to perfect his metaphysical system through research
into the notion of a universal cause of all being, attempting to arrive at a
starting point that would reduce reasoning to an algebra
of thought. He also continued his developments in mathematics; in 1681 he was
concerned with the proportion between a circle and a circumscribed square and,
in 1684, with the resistance of solids. In the latter year he published Nova
Methodus pro Maximis et Minimis ("New
Method for the Greatest and the Least"), which was an exposition of his
differential calculus.
Leibniz' noted Meditationes de Cognitione,
Veritate et Ideis
(Reflections on Knowledge, Truth, and Ideas) appeared at this time and
defined his theory of knowledge: things are not seen in God--as Nicolas Malebranche suggested--but rather there is an analogy, a
strict relation, between God's ideas and man's, an identity between God's logic
and man's. In February 1686, Leibniz wrote his Discours
de métaphysique (Discourse on Metaphysics). In
the March publication of Acta, he
disclosed his dynamics in a piece entitled Brevis
Demonstratio Erroris Memorabilis Cartesii et Aliorum Circa Legem Naturae ("Brief
Demonstration of the Memorable Error of Descartes and Others About the Law of
Nature"). A further development of Leibniz' views, revealed in a text
written in 1686 but long unpublished, was his generalization concerning propositions
that in every true affirmative proposition, whether necessary or contingent,
the predicate is contained in the notion of the subject. It can be said that,
at this time, with the exception of the word monad
(which did not appear until 1695), his philosophy of monadology
was defined.
In 1685 Leibniz
was named historian for the House of Brunswick and, on this occasion, Hofrat ("court adviser"). His job
was to prove, by means of genealogy, that the princely house had its origins in
the House of Este, an Italian princely family, which
would allow Hanover to lay claim to a ninth electorate. In search of these documents,
Leibniz began travelling in November 1687. Going by way of southern Germany, he
arrived in Austria, where he learned that Louis XIV had once again declared a
state of war; in Vienna, he was well received by the Emperor; he then went to
Italy. Everywhere he went, he met scientists and continued his scholarly work,
publishing essays on the movement of celestial bodies and on the duration of
things. He returned to Hanover in mid-July 1690. His efforts had not been in
vain. In October 1692 Ernest Augustus obtained the electoral investiture.
Until the end of
his life, Leibniz continued his duties as historian. He did not, however,
restrict himself to a genealogy of the House of Brunswick; he enlarged his goal
to a history of the Earth, which included such matters as geological events and
descriptions of fossils. He searched by way of monuments and linguistics for
the origins and migrations of peoples; then for the birth and progress of the
sciences, ethics, and politics; and, finally, for the elements of a historia sacra. In this project of a
universal history, Leibniz never lost sight of the fact that everything
interlocks. Even though he did not succeed in writing this history, his effort
was influential because he devised new combinations of old ideas and invented
totally new ones.
In 1691 Leibniz
was named librarian at Wolfenbüttel and propagated
his discoveries by means of articles in scientific journals. In 1695 he
explained a portion of his dynamic theory of motion in the Système
nouveau ("New System"), which treated the relationship of
substances and the preestablished harmony between the soul and the body:
God does not need to bring about man's action by means of his thoughts, as Malebranche asserted, or to wind some sort of watch in
order to reconcile the two; rather, the Supreme Watchmaker has so exactly
matched body and soul that they correspond--they give meaning to each
other--from the beginning. In 1697, De Rerum Originatione (On the Ultimate Origin of Things) tried
to prove that the ultimate origin of things can be none other than God. In
1698, De Ipsa Natura ("On
Nature Itself") explained the internal activity of nature in terms of
Leibniz' theory of dynamics.
All of these
writings opposed Cartesianism, which was judged to be
damaging to faith. Plans for the creation of German academies followed in rapid
succession. With the help of the electress Sophia
Charlotte, daughter of Ernest Augustus and soon to become the first queen of
Prussia (January 1701), the German Academy of Sciences in Berlin was founded on
July 11, 1700.
On Jan. 23, 1698,
Ernest Augustus died, and his son, George
Louis, succeeded him. Leibniz found himself confronted with an uneducated,
boorish prince, a reveller who kept him in the background. Leibniz took
advantage of every pretext to leave Hanover; he was constantly on the move; his
only comfort lay in his friendship with Sophia Charlotte and her mother,
Princess Sophia. Once again, he set to work on the reunion of the church: in
Berlin, it was a question of uniting the Lutherans and the Calvinists; in
Paris, he had to subdue Bishop Bénigne Bossuet's opposition; in Vienna (to which Leibniz returned
in 1700) he enlisted the support of the Emperor, which carried great weight; in
England, it was the Anglicans who needed convincing.
The death in
England of William, duke of Gloucester, in 1700 made George Louis,
great-grandson of James I, a possible heir to the throne. It fell to Leibniz,
jurist and historian, to develop his arguments concerning the rights of the
House of Braunschweig-Lüneburg with respect to this
succession.
The War of the
Spanish Succession began in March 1701 and did not come to a close until
September 1714, with the Treaty of Baden. Leibniz followed its episodes as a
patriot hostile to Louis XIV. His fame as a philosopher and scientist had by
this time spread all over Europe; he was named a foreign member by the Academy
of Sciences of Paris in 1700 and was in correspondence with most of the
important European scholars of the day. If he was publishing little at this
point, it was because he was writing Théodicée,
which was published in 1710. In this work he set down his ideas on divine
justice.
Leibniz was
impressed with the qualities of the Russian tsar Peter the Great, and in
October 1711 the ruler received him for the first time. Following this, he
stayed in Vienna until September 1714, and during this time the Emperor
promoted him to the post of Reichhofrat ("adviser
to the empire") and gave him the title of Freiherr
("baron"). About this time he wrote the Principes
de la nature et de la Grâce fondés en raison, which inaugurated a kind of preestablished harmony between these two orders. Further,
in 1714 he wrote the Monadologia, which synthesized the philosophy of
the Théodicée. In August 1714, the
death of Queen Anne brought George Louis to the English throne under the name
of George I. Returning to Hanover, where he was virtually placed under house
arrest, Leibniz set to work once again on the Annales
Imperii Occidentis Brunsvicenses (1843-46; "Braunschweig
Annals of the Western Empire"). At Bad-Pyrmont,
he met with Peter the Great for the last time in June 1716. From that point on,
he suffered greatly from gout and was confined to his bed until his death.
Leibniz was a man
of medium height with a stoop, broad-shouldered but bandy-legged, as capable of
thinking for several days sitting in the same chair as of travelling the roads
of Europe summer and winter. He was an indefatigable worker, a universal letter
writer (he had more than 600 correspondents), a patriot and cosmopolitan, a
great scientist, and one of the most powerful spirits of Western civilization.
With the logical work of the German
mathematician, philosopher, and diplomat Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, we
encounter one of the great triumphs, and tragedies, in the history of logic. He
created in the 1680s a symbolic
logic (see illustration
illustration: Representations
of the universal affirmative, "All A's are B's" in modern logic.
) that is remarkably similar to George
Boole's system of 1847--and Boole
is widely regarded as the initiator of mathematical or symbolic logic. But
nothing other than vague generalities about Leibniz' goals for logic was
published until 1903--well after symbolic logic was in full blossom. Thus one
could say that, great though Leibniz' discoveries were, they were virtually
without influence in the history of logic. (There remains some slight
possibility that Lambert or Boole may have been
directly or indirectly influenced by Leibniz' logical system.)
Leibniz' logical research was
not entirely symbolic, however, nor was he without influence in the history of
(nonsymbolic) logic. Early in his life, Leibniz was
strongly interested in the program of Lull,
and he wrote the De
arte combinatoria (1666); this work followed
the general Lullian goal of discovering truths by
combining concepts into judgments in exhaustive ways and then methodically assessing
their truth. Leibniz later developed a goal of devising what he called a "universally
characteristic language" (lingua characteristica
universalis) that would, first, notationally represent concepts by displaying the more
basic concepts of which they were composed, and second, naturally represent (in
the manner of graphs or pictures, "iconically")
the concept in a way that could be easily grasped by readers, no matter what
their native tongue. Leibniz studied and was impressed by the method of the
Egyptians and Chinese in using picturelike
expressions for concepts. The goal of a universal language had already been
suggested by Descartes
for mathematics as a "universal mathematics"; it had also been
discussed extensively by the English philologist George Dalgarno
(c. 1626-87) and, for mathematical language and communication, by the
French algebraist François
Viète (1540-1603). The search for a universal
language to replace Latin was seriously taken up again in the late 19th
century, first by Giuseppe
Peano--whose work on Interlingua,
an uninflected form of Latin, was directly inspired by Leibniz' conception--and
then with Esperanto. The goal of a logical language also inspired Gottlob Frege, and in the 20th
century it prompted the development of the logical language Loglan
and the computer language Prolog.
Another and distinct goal
Leibniz proposed for logic was a "calculus of reason" (calculus
ratiocinator). This would naturally first require a symbolism but would then
involve explicit manipulations of the symbols according to established rules by
which either new truths could be discovered or
proposed conclusions could be checked to see if they could indeed be derived
from the premises. Reasoning
could then take place in the way large sums are done--that is, mechanically or
algorithmically--and thus not be subject to individual mistakes and failures of
ingenuity. Such derivations could be checked by others or performed by machines,
a possibility that Leibniz seriously contemplated. Leibniz' suggestion that
machines could be constructed to draw valid inferences or to check the
deductions of others was followed up by Charles
Babbage, William
Stanley Jevons, and Charles
Sanders Peirce and his student Allan Marquand in the 19th century, and with wide success on
modern computers
after World War II.
The symbolic calculus that
Leibniz devised seems to have been more of a calculus of reason than a
"characteristic" language. It was motivated by his view that most concepts
were "composite": they were collections or conjunctions of other more
basic concepts. Symbols (letters, lines, or circles) were then used to stand
for concepts and their relationships. This resulted in what is called an "intensional" rather than an "extensional"
logic--one whose terms stand for properties or concepts rather than for the
things having these properties. Leibniz' basic notion of the truth
of a judgment was that the concepts making up the predicate were "included
in" the concept of the subject. What Leibniz symbolized as "A ,"
or what we might write as "A = B" was that all the concepts making up
concept A also are contained in concept B, and vice versa.
Leibniz used two further
notions to expand the basic logical calculus. In his notation, "A B
C"
indicates that the concepts in A and those in B wholly
constitute those in C. We might write this as "A + B = C" or "A B
= C"--if we keep in mind that A, B, and C stand for concepts or
properties, not for individual things. Leibniz also used the juxtaposition of
terms in the following way: "AB C,"
which we might write as "A B
= C" or "A B
= C," signifies in his system that all the concepts in both A and B wholly
constitute the concept C.
A universal
affirmative judgment, such as "All A's are B's," becomes in
Leibniz' notation "A AB."
This equation states that the concepts included in the concepts of both A and B
are the same as those in A. A syllogism, "All A's are B's; all B's are
C's; therefore all A's are C's," becomes the sequence of equations "A
= AB; B =BC; therefore A =AC." This conclusion can be derived from the
premises by two simple algebraic substitutions and the associativity
of logical multiplication. Leibniz' interpretation of particular and negative
statements was more problematic. Although he later seemed to prefer an
algebraic, equational symbolic logic, he experimented
with many alternative techniques, including graphs.
As with many early symbolic
logics, including many developed in the 19th century, Leibniz' system had
difficulties with particular and negative statements, and it included little
discussion of propositional logic and no formal treatment of quantified
relational statements. (Leibniz later became keenly aware of the importance of
relations and relational inferences.) Although Leibniz might seem to deserve to
be credited with great originality in his symbolic logic--especially in his equational, algebraic logic--it turns out that such
insights were relatively common to mathematicians of the 17th and 18th
centuries who had a knowledge of traditional
syllogistic logic. In 1685 Jakob Bernoulli published a pamphlet on the parallels
of logic and algebra and gave some algebraic renderings of categorical
statements. Later the symbolic work of Lambert, Ploucquet,
Euler, and even Boole--all apparently uninfluenced by
Leibniz' or even Bernoulli's work--seems to show the extent to which these
ideas were apparent to the best mathematical minds of the day.